Film Review: Hannah Arendt and the “Banality of Evil”

“Hannah Arendt” film poster: Zeitgeist Films.

At the end of the Second World War in 1945, Nazi war criminal Adolph Eichmann escaped to Argentina. There he was discovered by Israeli intelligence agents who kidnapped him in 1961 and flew him to Israel to be tried for genocide against the Jewish people.

Hannah Arendt (1906-1975), a German-born Jewish political theorist and journalist who emigrated to America in 1941, was commissioned by the New Yorker to attend the Eichmann trial and write about it for the magazine.

Her report inaugurated a controversy about what she called “the banality of evil” that today, half a century later, remains unresolved. This controversy, which split apart Arendt’s circle of family and friends, stands at the heart of this film.

Click here to view the Internet trailer for this film.

Eichmann had been a high-level administrator in the Third Reich, responsible for organizing the transport of millions of Jews to death camps. In the Jerusalem courtroom he was placed inside a bullet-proof glass cage for his own protection and subjected to a trial that went on for fourteen months. The proceedings were televised and exposed the man and his crimes to an international audience.

Arendt collage: Raymond Barglow.

The prosecution’s evidence included the testimony of Jewish survivors, who described their death camp experiences in horrifying detail. While she was moved by these eye-witness accounts, Arendt took exception to the political messaging that the trial broadcast to the world. It seemed to her that Israeli leaders such as Ben Gurion meant to use the trial to expose, through the example of Eichmann, a fanatical anti-Semitism that had motivated the Nazis and that continued to endanger Israel. Hence Eichmann had to be tried and judged as a heartless and relentless murderer of Jews specifically, not as a perpetrator of “crimes against humanity” that victimized homosexuals, gypsies, Communists and socialists as well.

When Arendt sat in the courtroom and witnessed the proceedings, she found herself disagreeing with the prosecution’s narrative. But her counter-narrative seemed to many of those who followed the trial to disrespect the Jewish victims of the Holocaust and to exonerate their executioners. In fact, her report on the Eichmann trial unleashed an international debate. Whereas the court made Eichmann out to be a depraved monster, Arendt regarded him instead as “terribly and terrifyingly normal.”

Eichmann trial: Wikimedia Commons/United States Holocaust Memorial Museum.

In director Magaretha van Trotta’s presentation of this dispute, she draws outstanding performances from her lead actress Barbara Sukowa, who is compelling as Arendt, and from the German actors playing her close friends Hans Jonas and Kurt Blumenfeld. Sukowa wonderfully conveys those paradoxical qualities of Arendt that were well-known to her friends: warmth and kindness on the one hand, and on the other a fierce independence and confidence in her own judgment that sometimes estranged her profoundly from others.

The film represents both Jonas and Blumenfeld as bitterly critical of Arendt’s opinion that Eichmann was merely a “conformist” with no strong anti-Semitic convictions. They were further offended by what they perceived as her shifting of blame from Eichmann to the Jewish people themselves, when she wrote that Jewish community councils in Europe cooperated with the Nazis in implementing the “Final Solution.” Arendt goes so far as to say, “To a Jew this role of the Jewish leaders in the destruction of their own people is undoubtedly the darkest chapter of the whole dark story.” Jonas and Blumenfeld found such remarks preposterous, anti-Semitic, and out of keeping with Arendt’s own personal history.

Like Arendt, Jonas and Blumenfeld were German Jews who had escaped the Nazi regime during the 1930s. Jonas and Arendt had become close friends in the 1920s when they both were students of the German philosopher Martin Heidegger, who would go on to collaborate with the Nazis in the 1930s. Arendt became romantically involved with Heidegger, and the film makes much of their tumultuous relationship. Hans Jonas taught at the New School in New York and wrote about ethics and religion. His reflections on caring for the earth and its future influenced the German Green Party in the 1980s. Kurt Blumenfeld, who had been Arendt’s political mentor and friend during the pre-war years in Germany, was a charismatic Zionist activist and orator who went to Palestine in 1933.

Friends of Arendt such as Jonas and Blumenfeld repudiated what they took to be her misunderstanding of the aims of the Jerusalem trial and her willingness to explain away the crimes of the accused. The film gives a voice to both sides of this dispute, although Arendt’s perspective is more fully explained. Since the cinematic subject here is Hanna Arendt, this favoritism is appropriate. Still, the audience receives a somewhat one-sided view of the contested issues. The film exaggerates, moreover, the isolation and danger to Arendt that resulted from the controversy. This is most evident in a scene that shows Israeli intelligence agents confronting Arendt walking on a country road and urging her not to publish her report on the Eichmann trial – an incident that the director has fabricated.

Still, it is true that Israeli leaders were incensed by Arendt’s report. The trial’s chief prosecutor, Gideon Hausner, visited the United States to speak against Arendt’s views. Fierce repudiation came also from outside Israel, at the hands of critics like Nahum Goldmann, President of the World Jewish Congress. The American Jewish Congress vehemently attacked Arendt’s views, and the Anti-Defamation League condemned Arendt’s book as itself “evil.” Norman Podhoretz, editor of Commentary, wrote that Arendt’s portrait of Eichmann “violates everything we know about the Nature of Man.… No person could have joined the Nazi Party, let alone the S.S., who was not at the very least a vicious anti-Semite …” And in 1965, Jacob Robinson, who had advised the prosecution during the Eichmann trial, published a scholarly 400-page refutation of Arendt’s views.

Hannah Arendt, Wikimedia Commons/Peter Steiner and Regina Steiner.

Arendt’s interpretation of the Eichmann trial was all the more baffling to her friends and colleagues because it seemed so distant from her work in decades past on behalf of Zionist causes. In her youth Arendt had admired the idealism and courage of fervent Zionists like Blumenfeld, and she too had endorsed the project of creating a Jewish homeland in Palestine. But as time went on and the Zionist project culminated in the creation of a Jewish state that excluded its Arab population from full citizenship, her reservations about this particular way of fulfilling the promise of Zionism amplified. Along with Jewish spokespersons such as the philosopher Martin Buber and the reform rabbi Judah Magnes, she anticipated that the establishment of Israel as a religious state might rule out peaceful coexistence between the new nation and its Palestinian population and Arab neighbors. “I am not against Israel in principle,” she insisted, “I am against certain important Israeli policies.”

In the 1940s, Arendt supported the creation of a Jewish homeland as an inclusive, bi-national “federated state” governed by “Jewish-Arab community councils.” This proposal struck many Zionists and anti-Zionists alike as naïve and unrealistic, given the long-standing and deep antagonisms between these two peoples.

Still, Arendt was prescient in recognizing the dangers to Israel of unceasing violent conflict with the Arab world and of a siege mentality within Israel itself. In Arendt’s view, Israel’s reliance upon military force to defeating Palestinian resistance was more likely to exacerbate the conflict than to bring about a peaceful resolution.

“Rosa Luxemburg” film poster: Delphi, Nordlingen Germany.

The controversy following publication of Arendt’s report on the Jerusalem trial might have subsided if it had not re-awakened an older, perennial dispute within Judaism about what is more important: the safety and flourishing of the Jewish people or the creation of a more humane and just world.

Since Biblical times, facing oppression or even extermination, Jews have been compelled to “look after our own” in order to survive. This preoccupation with self-protection led to the creation of Israel, a homeland for the Jewish people, in 1948.

Coexisting with this inward-looking, survivalist mentality has always been another, wider identification, universal in its scope, that reaches out to the “Other” – the oppressed and marginalized and fallen of all lands. Torah has it that the Jewish people is to be a “light unto the nations,” remembering that “you shall love the stranger as yourself, for you were strangers in the land of Egypt.”

Conflict between these two traditions within Judaism drives the plot forward in van Trotta’s film. Along with Kurt Blumenfeld and Hans Jonas, another friend of Arendt, the Jewish Kabbalah scholar and Zionist Gershom Scholem, repudiated her report on the trial of Eichmann, finding its tone “heartless,” “malicious,” and contemptuous. In a letter to Arendt in 1963, he wrote that “In the Jewish tradition there is a concept, hard to define and yet concrete enough, which we know as Ahabath Israel, or Love for the Jewish people.’ In you, dear Hannah, as in so many intellectuals who came from the German left, I find no trace of this.”

Arendt wrote back to Scholem, “How right you are that I have no such love, and for two reasons: first, I have never in my life “loved” some nation or collective — not the German, French or American nation, or the working class, or anything of that kind.  Indeed I love ‘only’ my friends and am quite incapable of any other kind of love.”

Identification with a nation, culture, or faith is for Arendt not a foundation for love: “this kind of love for the Jews would seem suspect to me, since I’m Jewish myself….. We would both agree that patriotism is impossible without constant opposition and critique.  In this entire affair I can confess to you one thing: the injustice committed by my own people naturally provokes me more than injustice done by others.”

The historical disputes within Judaism influenced the interpretations that were given to the Eichmann trial in 1961. Whereas the prosecution was intent on demonstrating that Eichmann manifested an anti-Semitic hatred to which Jewish communities had been subjected for many centuries, Arendt perceived Eichmann as emblematic of a new kind of evil that arises in modern, bureaucratic societies and whose targets are not only Jews.

The director of this film, although clearly sympathetic to Arendt’s perspective, steps back from endorsement of any single interpretation of the trial, choosing instead to have the trial speak for itself: rather than having an actor enact the role of Eichmann, van Trotta has inserted actual televised footage of the trial. Hence, the film audience confronts the same question that divided observers of the proceedings: who is this man, Adolph Eichmann? Can we make sense of his motives? And how typical were such motives among Nazis who planned and carried out the “Final Solution”?

The prosecutors at the trial in Jerusalem set out to establish malevolent intent on the part of Eichmann, but Arendt found no trace of such criminal motivation in the man. Indeed, given the massive human suffering and death for which he was responsible, Eichmann seemed to many observers, not only to Arendt, remarkably bland and ordinary – the very model of the faceless, unemotional bureaucrat. By his own account, he had been merely a “cog in the machine,” obediently carrying out the orders of his superiors.

Arendt’s appraisal of Eichmann seemed to her critics to accept naively and mistakenly this picture of the man and his motivations. They pointed out the historical record of Eichmann’s anti-Semitism, his full embrace of Nazi ideology, and the evidence for his personal as well as official cruelty and sadism.

Arendt’s account of Eichmann was not, however, oblivious to the considerations that the prosecution detailed. She rejected the excuses for this behavior that Eichmann gave, regarded him as guilty, and agreed with the court’s death penalty verdict.

Defenders of Arendt have pointed out, moreover, that when she described Eichmann as “thoughtless,” she meant that he did not deliberate in any critical way about his own actions and their consequences, and was incapable of thinking from the standpoint of another person. Hence Eichmann might have been “thoughtless,” in the sense Arendt intended, and a doctrinaire anti-Semite. Being an unquestioning, model bureaucrat – “neither perverted no sadistic,” as Arendt described Eichmann — is compatible with being a zealous ideologue.

Arendt had herself — in The Origins of Totalitarianism, published in 1951, a decade before the Eichmann trial — linked bureaucratic action to ideological conviction. She argued there that during the Third Reich, for example, ideology had enabled totalitarianism by encouraging blind nationalism, suspicion of the designated “other,” and militarism.

Even if Arendt misjudged Eichmann’s character, she clearly identified a feature of 20th-century state-sanctioned violence with her telling phrase “the banality of evil.” What Arendt explains to us, writes criminologist Daniel Maier-Katkin, is that “When the devil comes to negotiate for our souls, he brings attractive gifts and rationalizations, and is more likely to be wearing a business suit or uniform of national pride than a fiery cape.”

Unshakeable ideological conviction results from such “gifts and rationalizations”; it insists upon a certain self-justifying story for one’s actions and illustrates that story with compelling images and stereotypes about a black-and-white world. In her report on the trial of Eichmann, Arendt wrote of a self-serving fiction or “tape” that played over and over again in his mind, “and it was this taped memory that showed itself to be proof against reason and argument and information and insight of any kind.” Eichmann’s unthinking conformity allowed him to square his policy decisions with his conscience.

The trial of Eichmann presented in stark terms one man’s repudiation of conscience, but also showcased, through the testimony of more than one hundred witnesses, most of whom were concentration camp survivors, the genocidal crimes of the Third Reich. It may be true, as Arendt alleged, that the trial served particular political aims — that it was used by leaders of Israel to present their justification for Israeli policies in a world perceived as incorrigibly hostile. Director van Trotta says, though, that she respects the wish of the trial organizers to remind the world of the Holocaust. “I understand Ben-Gurion more than she [Arendt] did. I am German, not Jewish. I understood … because in our country, the younger people of my generation didn’t know anything, and our parents didn’t tell us.”

Van Trotta’s film on Arendt and “the banality of evil” not only restores memory but also might remind us of contemporary violent conflicts, including the Israeli-Palestinian one. The narratives told on both sides promote an unremitting hostility that over the past century has stymied efforts to make peace. These narratives, combining personal memory with cultural tradition, have fostered distrust and demonization of the Other. As Rabbi Michael Lerner points out, both sides “embraced nationalist rhetoric …. Both sides were traumatized by their own history, and by outrageous acts of violence perpetrated by the other.”

Palestinian children in a school wrecked by an Israeli bomb: Majdi Fathi, Gaza.

 

Three Israelis killed by a Hamas rocket attack: Sheera Frankel.

 

At the same time, though, the recognition that ordinary people can, under certain conditions, commit horrendous acts opens the possibility of historical transformation. In his article, “Arendt’s Banality of Evil Thesis and the Arab-Israeli Conflict,” Israeli political theorist Yaron Ezrahi submits that “If both Israelis and Palestinians were able to attribute the acts of violence and crimes committed by each side against the other as related to particular circumstances rather than to essential character traits, they could more easily focus on manageable changes …. The ability to recognize that even terrorists are humans who were turned by religion, ideology, and suffering into suicide bombers or that trigger-happy Israeli soldiers are themselves victims of prejudice, brainwashing, improper education, and distorting emotional manipulation, is a first step.”

But that first step toward peace is the most difficult one! It’s blocked by the stories people tell about the unforgivable wrongs they have suffered. Arendt submitted, though (in her Denktagebuch, the diary she wrote when she returned to Germany in 1950), that reconciliation requires not that we no longer condemn certain actions of the past, but rather that we recast our memories and our fears within a wider context of understanding that remains true to history while also enabling a fair and successful path forward.

More

5 thoughts on “Film Review: Hannah Arendt and the “Banality of Evil”

  1. I very much appreciate the clear and constrained way that Mr. Barglow describes the shortcomings in Arendt’s analysis of Eichmann. At the very end, he brilliantly finds value in her “banality of evil” idea (however misunderstood and misapplied it may be regarding Eichmann) for resolving the Israeli-Palestinian conflict.

  2. You stated, “Eichmann’s unthinking conformity allowed him to square his policy decisions with his conscience.” Mr. Barglow, you could not be more wrong. Eichmann had no conscience because he was a psychopath. Would you and your readers kindly look at Hare’s psychopathy checklist? A psychopath can outwardly appear to be quite normal and even charming. When the Third Reich took over, all of the psychopaths came crawling out of the woodwork. A normal police officer would not go out and murder innocent civilians, including women and children, just because he was ordered to. But a psychopathic cop would. The Arab-Israeli conflict doesn’t have anything to do with Eichmann or the Holocaust.

  3. Eichmann was no psychopath, not even an anti-Semite. He was what we call a-hundred-fifty-percenter. To please his bosses he excelled in his job in order to reach admiration. That was his goal in life. If you scrutinize society you will always find this type of men. It’s a simple thing and the wording of “the banality of evil” hits the nail on the head.

  4. I just saw the “Hannah Arendt” movie and the jury for me, is still out. Certainly human beings are top of the evolutionary line—sentient: “creatures born with a conscience” Is there something about the times, something about German culture, or the economic conditions of Germany after WWI, that created a fertile environment,for Hitler’s totaltarianism, to survive, in a short span of history? More investigation is required. Thank you!